September 22, 2014
Welcome to The Nurkse School Ideas Bank / Tere tulemast Nurkse instituudi Ideedepanka
1. Oleme ikka elus ja blogime jälle üle pika aja!
2. Oleme vahepeal muutunud Ragnar Nurkse innovatsiooni ja valitsemise instituudiks: www.ttu.ee/nurkse
3. Meie blogi on edaspidi aktiivsem ja ilusamas kohas - The Nurkse School Ideas Bank: http://nurkseschool.tumblr.com/
4. Meid saab jälgida ka läbi Facebooki, Twitteri (@NurkseSchool) ja rss-i: http://nurkseschool.tumblr.com/rss
5. Seda blogi enam ei uuendata.
We have several great news:
1. We are still alive and blogging again after some time!
2. We have become the Ragnar Nurkse School of Innovation and Governance: www.ttu.ee/nurkse
3. Our blog will be more active and nicer to enjoy - The Nurkse School Ideas Bank: http://nurkseschool.tumblr.com/
4. We can be followed and liked also in Facebook, Twitter (@NurkseSchool) and via rss:
http://nurkseschool.tumblr.com/rss
5. This blog will not be updated anymore.
March 30, 2012
Lae kehtestamine sotsiaalmaksu pensionikindlustuse osale
By Ringa Raudla, Vanemteadur, Avaliku Halduse Instituut, Tallinna Tehnikaülikool
October 11, 2011
Vaesus – sotsiaalne norm?
December 6, 2010
Is addressing fragmented EU Aid useful without focussing on productive capacity?
October 5, 2010
Inflation vs. the Autonomous Individual
Recently, I have argued that the notorious German fear of inflation, allegedly based on Weimar Republic experiences of hyperinflation, is not irrational but very rational indeed, not because of history, but because of the present. In a recent contribution entitled "In Praise of Inflation", James Surowiecki, in my opinion probably the best economics journalist currently active (not surprising as he writes for The New Yorker, the thinking person’s Economist, and then some), explains why moderate inflation as such is often good for the economy and that fear of inflation as such, and anywhere, is irrational. He concludes by saying,
This intuitive prejudice against inflation may not be purely rational, but in normal times it’s beneficial: it encourages sober habits and discourages quick fixes. But, in times of crisis, other policies may succeed where pure rectitude can’t. … the economy doesn’t exist, in the end, to reward virtue and punish vice. It exists to maximize our well-being, and, currently, doing that may require helping the undeserving and irresponsible, if only because there are so many of them. Boosting inflation isn’t the right policy, but it may just be the correct one.
But as is well-known, there are beneficial aspects of inflation well beyond crisis times. This is of course Keynes’ argument, i.e., to quote Rainer Kattel,
Inflation is actually a form of the hermeneutical circle: the way we think the future will pan out changes our current economic behavior. If we think prices won't rise, or even fall, then why should we consume or invest now, since if the real value of our savings is bound to grow, postponing economic activity and hoarding cash makes a lot of sense. However, if everybody does that, we will get a stagnating economy that might easily end up in a crisis. That, and not crisis investment, is the main Keynesian argument for government spending and deficits.
Also, the other way around, if we think that prices will be very volatile in the future, again why should we consume or invest now? However, if we assume that there will be a moderate growth in prices, it makes a lot of sense to consume or invest now, as this way, we can profit from current lower prices and by investing actually reap future higher prices. In that sense, moderate inflation is a function of moderate growth as well. That's why Keynes thought that government should essentially always run deficits, as this way, there's always slightly more money around than really needed and thus there's moderate inflation that then feedbacks into economic behavior.
And of course, in situations with high debt levels, moderate inflation is doubly interesting or good as it favors current investment over past debts and current savings.
The problem with inflation, however, crisis or no crisis, is that “the people” don’t like it much. As Surowiecki explains,
A 2001 study that looked at the “macroeconomics of happiness” found that higher inflation put a severe dent in how happy people reported themselves to be. The distaste for inflation is such that a 1996 study (titled, aptly, “Why Do People Dislike Inflation?”), by the Yale economist Robert Shiller, found that, in countries around the world, sizable majorities said that they would prefer low inflation and high unemployment to high inflation and low unemployment, even if that meant that millions of extra people would go without work.
So, naturally, the challenge to good economists and policy-makers is, according to Surowiecki, to explain to the people why moderate inflation is actually in their own interest.
Or is it? That depends on what economics is for. Keynes, in a speech towards the end of his life, declared that economists are the "trustees, not of civilization, but of the possibility of civilization." The entire idea of democracy is to prevent experts, who do not only think they know best, but who actually do know best, from making the final decisions, because the rule of the expert does not exactly have a good track record in human history. (And the reasons for that are, among other things, that we cannot agree on what is best; that if we could, we couldn’t communicate it; that human happiness is a moving target; and so on and so on.) Our civilization, from the polis to today’s democracy, from public sphere to public policy, is based on the assumption of autonomous individuals who can make up their own minds and who have a meaningful idea of what is good for them. They make the basic choices, and those basic choices actually form what the polis, the comune, the state in the end is about (Leo Strauss’ point) – because choices could be otherwise as well, but they are the way they are, yet they can and do develop. The Good Life in the Good State, Aristotle’s goal of living together in a structured manner in place and time, is objectively ascertainable, but it rests on the combination of subjective decisions regarding what the Good Life actually is. Economics, again, is to enable this; it’s not a substitute for the Good Life – it’s a means, not an end.
If that is so, if a majority of people, everywhere on the globe, say that they'd rather not have inflation, because for them, monetary stability is more important, for a variety of reasons (choosing not to reward the unworthy; choosing as much stability and predictability as possible as high priorities in life), and if they know what the negative effects may be or even will be (and of course, in economics this is never fully clear), then if one basically believes in those autonomous individuals – and the form of human consociation based on this, which is Democracy –, this is a very strong argument in favor of currency stability and against inflation.
In other words, my point is that the popular anti-inflation stand, according to Shiller’s indeed still extremely interesting research, may not be just good or bad economics but rather, like institutions such as private property or monogamous marriage, a way-of-life choice within the polis, and thus beyond the say of the expert.
Of course, these things can change. Of course, things have been different – memories of William Jennings Bryan and the "Cross of Gold" come up. Of course, happiness research has always suggested, and now has come to the agenda again (such as Derek Bok in a recent book) that people do not know what makes them really happy. Of course, in a moderately rational world, people should pay attention to rational arguments. Of course, if one feels strongly that inflation increases human happiness, one should do what one can to make people see this. And thus, the discourse can and must be kept open.
But still, fear of inflation, if, as I suggest, it at least often is really based on choice and priority setting, however subconsciously, is not irrational then, because basic world-view-based goals are beyond the rational/irrational divide – that divide is about questions of how to achieve those goals. That may be very regrettable indeed from an economic policy perspective, but many of our choices are like that. In the end, what matters isn’t the correct policy, but rather the right one, and the system in which we have chosen to live, Democracy, has been set up precisely to make the chances higher that sometimes, the right things are actually done – or at least that the wrong ones are avoided as often as possible.
September 10, 2010
Tööandjate manifesti tähendusest
By Erkki Karo
Majanduse struktuursete muutuste üle on võimalik arutleda nii emotsionaalselt ja omakasupüüdlikult kui ka neutraalselt ja analüütiliselt. Kumba mõttemaailma võiks kuuluda Tööandjate manifest? Ametiühingute eestkõnelejad ning isegi peaminister on sildistanud manifesti esimesse kategooriasse, kuid neid silte on seatud suuresti samamoodi emotsionaalselt ja ehk ka isiklikest huvidest lähtuvalt.
2008. aastal ilmus innovatsiooni ja tehnoloogilise arengu uuringute valdkonnas raamat Small Country Innovation Systems (toimetanud Charles Edquist ja Leif Hommen), mis võrdleb omavahel viite kiire tehnoloogilise arengu ja majanduskasvuga majandust (Aasia tiigrid ja Iirimaa) ning viite küpsema majandusstruktuuriga ja väiksema kasvudünaamikaga arenenud riiki (Skandinaavia riigid ja Holland). Sellest raamatust võib tuua välja huvitavaid mõtteid ja järeldusi, mis võiksid olla olulised ka praeguse Tööandjate manifesti sisu ja reaktsioonide valguses.
Ühe huvitava paradoksina tuuakse raamatus välja järeldus, et kui vaadata erinevate riikide suutlikkust seada prioriteete majanduspoliitika struktuursete arengute kujundamisel, strateegiliste valikute tegemisel ja poliitikate koordineerimisel (n. migratsiooni- ja maksupoliitika sidumine tööstus- või innovatsioonipoliitikaga jne.), siis kiiresti arenevad Aasia riigid on suutnud seda teha lihtsamini ja efektiivsemalt, kui küpset heaoluühiskonda esindavad Skandinaavia riigid. Skandinaavia riikidele heidetakse ette, et viimastel kümnenditel on nende tegelik arengupotentsiaal pidurdunud ning järjest keerulisemaks on muutunud strateegiliste poliitikate kujundamine ja valikute tegemine. Selle tulemusena on riiklikud majanduspoliitikad muutunud hägusaks ning ei oma piisavalt olulist mõju majanduse sisulistele arengutele, et käia kaasas tehnoloogiliste muutustega. Samas väidetakse, et nüüdseks on need tendentsid üha enam esile kerkimas ka kiire arenguga Aasia riikides.
Huvitaval kombel ei seletata seda paradoksi mitte liiga suure riigi või liiga keeruliste poliitikatega, mida riik ei ole võimeline ellu viima. Vastupidi, raamatu autorid väidavad, et põhjused, miks kiire arenguga riigid on varasemalt suutnud ellu viia tugevaid ja kohenemisvõimelisi poliitikaid ning küpsed riigid on viljelenud pigem struktuurseid arenguid mittetoetavaid hägusaid poliitikaid, seisnevad hoopiski poliitikaid mõjutavate huvigruppide koosseisudes ja tugevuses.
Raamatus väidetakse (hüpoteesi tasandil), et Aasia tiigrid saavutasid majanduskasvu ja tehnoloogilise arengu, kuna nende arengutee alguses puudusid ühiskonnas tugevad huvigrupid traditsioonilistes, kuid väheneva lisandväärtusega tööstusharudes, mille eesmärgiks oleks status quo säilitamine (ehk oma positsiooni säilitamine läbi suuremate riiklike toetuste või väiksemate riiklike piirangute ja koormiste). Seetõttu said ka riigid rakendada tugevate prioriteetidega poliitikaid ja viia ellu põhimõttelisi visioone, mis tagasid tehnoloogilise arengu ja majandusliku kasvu.
Tänaseks on aga Aasias esile kerkinud oht, et ‘eilsed’ uued tehnoloogiad ja tööstused on muutunud samasugusteks traditsioonilisteks valdkondadeks, kus lisandväärtus kaheneb, mistõttu tööstuste huvid ja ootused riiklike poliitikate suhtes on muutumas. Samamoodi, Skandinaavia riikides on raamatu autorite väitel viimastel kümnenditel olnud läbivaks oluliseks mõjuteguriks just traditsiooniliste tööstuste huvigrupid, kelle eesmärgiks on olnud status quo säilitamine, mis on võimalik läbi üldiste, häguste ja horisontaalsete poliitikate, mille peamiseks eesmärgiks ei ole majanduse struktuursete muutuste läbiviimine (horisontaalse poliitika näiteks võiks olla sotsiaalmaksu lagi kõikidele kõrgepalgalistele töökohtadele; tugevate prioriteetidega poliitika näiteks võiks olla sotisaalmaksu lagi IKT ja teiste kõrgtehnoloogiliste valdkondade T&A töötajatele vms.).
Innovatsiooni kontekstis räägivad nii visionäärid kui ka poliitikakujundajad väikeettevõtete, uute start-up’ide (n. IKT puhul poisid naabri garaažist) ja muude seni avaldumata ettevõtlikkuse initsiatiivide tähtsusest ja nende riikliku toetamise olulisusest. Tööandjate manifesti esitanud Tööandjate Keskliidu liikmeskonnas (ja ka nõukogus) on uute tehnoloogia valdkondade esindajad, väikeettevõtjad ja võimalikud uue ‘Eesti Nokia’ omanikud selgelt vähemuses.
Seega, kuigi me ei saa selgelt väita, et Eestis domineeriks tugevad traditsioonilised tööstusharud uute tärkavate tehnoloogia valdkondade üle, võivad huvigruppide mõjujooned ja eesmärgid poliitikas olla ühesemalt selged – eriti kui uutes tehnoloogiavaldkondades domineerivad väikeettevõtted, virtuaalsed ja globaalsed tegijad, võrgustikud jne., kellel ei ole kombeks rahvuslikke huvigruppe ja käegakatsutavaid kogukondi luua, või nendele loota.
Selles valguses, ehk on Tööandjate manifest ‘vanakooli’ (heas mõttes) meeste nägemus, mitte kõikide praeguste ja tulevaste tööandjate nägemus, mille kõrvale oleks vaja konkureerivat mõttekäiku ettevõtjatelt, kelle jaoks ei ole tulevik mitte 2011-2015, vaid kuskil kaugemal tehnoloogilise arengu trajektooril. Samas, kui selline mõttekäik on tõene, siis peaks ehk ka riik vaatama üle oma majanduspoliitika kujundamise mudeli, kus avaliku sektori poliitikakujundamise võimekuse asemel eelistatakse loota ettevõtlust ja tööstust esindavate organisatsioonide visioonide ja nägemuste peale. Kui viimased on selgelt ühele poole kaldu, siis on oht, et kogu majanduspoliitika kisub kreeni või ei vasta tuleviku ootustele ja vajadustele.
June 27, 2010
The Myth of German Inflation Fears
By Wolfgang Drechsler
Germany’s stubborn insistence on austerity rather than increased spending to stimulate economic recovery is the worst possible stand to take at the current moment of the global financial crisis; it shows that nothing has been learned from history, that Keynes is still not understood in Berlin and that at the end of the day, Europe, the European Union and the Euro, and even the world economy, may go down in flames because of German stupidity. And why are Germans being so stupid? Just because of the irrational fear of the repetition of history, the German hyperinflation of 1922-1923, an outright mythical event which until today conditions Germany’s (and that means the Germans’) attitude towards spending vs. savings. Politicians from Sarkozy via Barroso to Obama and opinion leaders from Krugman via Dean Baker to Soros agree on that, and you can read it in many of the current G-20 and G-8 statements and comments as well.
Nevertheless, this is complete nonsense. The myth here is not the German hyperinflation at all – the myth is that the German attitude towards austerity vs. demand stimulation is in any way significantly based on that historical event. How much does history really matter in Germany – at least, pre-World War II history? How much does the average German really know about the hyperinflation of yore? Next to nothing, I would say – the majority of Germans has probably never even heard of it, as horrible and disastrous an event as it was. But how much can the past really hold sway over the present? It seems to me that only the burned child shuns the fire and that among today’s German decision-makers, opinion leaders and citizens, almost nobody consciously remembers that time. If we say that in order to halfway understand what the inflation meant, you had to be 16 years old when it happened (otherwise this is too abstract a topic, rather than say a war), that means you had to be born by 1907 at the latest. In this case, you would be at least 103 today – which my philosophical teacher Hans-Georg Gadamer in fact was when he died in 2002, and he had remained a public intellectual until the end, but he is still a rare exception. Sure, the hyperinflation is used as an image, as a reference point, as an illustration, but not more – which is also my experience from Germany, where I am right now as well, and one side of my family even did suffer heavily during the hyperinflation. Hyperinflation references in the German media are usually to foreign statements, not to the event itself. Historical events that people don’t remember are not “real” – unless propaganda and/or family lore renarrate them again and again in such a way that they become immediate and relevant again, and the hyperinflation, as I mentioned, seems somehow too abstract and complex for that. In any case, whatever the reason, the hyperinflation is not “immediate”, as Gadamer would have said, in today’s Germany at all.
In order to understand the German attitude right now, therefore, especially if one is concerned about it and if one thinks it stands in the way of crisis-appropriate policy, it is important to discard this faith in the myth and to try to find out what the real reason for this harsh anti-inflation stand is. My answer is that Germany’s strict opposition to inflation is perfectly rational, the opposite of being myth-based, and that there is indeed a connex between spending policies and inflation. Many Germans, if not most (and certainly most of a key segment of the population, the large middle class which is the foundation of the political system), have their assets in currency-based investments and are not in debt, or at lest perceive themselves that way either for now or for the immediate future, and any inflation is a net loss for them, and they have paid into a (currently) very well-working social and medical insurance system that likewise appears to hinge on a stable currency. As their life quality and future rest on this, and as they were always and unequivocally promised again and again by all politicians, experts and bankers that the currency will remain stable, it’s hardly surprising that they would mind, and indeed mind very much indeed, if this were not the case anymore. I basically agree with Adolph Wagner of course that all private property is state-created rather than natural, indeed that it is a function of the state, but it’s hardly surprising that people want to at least keep what they have if they have been assured again and again that they may keep it.
Add to this that a positive overall effect of inflation on the German, and indeed European and global, economy can be claimed but not proven within our ruling episteme, i.e. the system that conditions what we take for true or false: Insisting on a low inflation might bring the entire system to a collapse, so that in the end, Germany would have to pay anyway, but it only might – some, perhaps many (but certainly not all) economists may claim that it does, but how does that add to any likelihood of it being true in the eyes of a well-informed German citizen? Thus, being totally opposed to inflation and to policies that are conducive to or even based on it, is entirely rational for a German citizen. This is also the systemically correct and even ethical position because democracy is based at least to some extent, and even to a necessary one, on voters voting their genuine interests as perceived.
But how can one call the rational pursuit of economic self-interest ethical? Well, one can if one is a Smithian in any case, but the key aspect to realize in this context is that if one claims that Germany should take up its responsibility for the welfare of Europe and the European Union and its fellow Europeans, one ignores that there is no European identity – yet – in Germany or elsewhere. Maybe there should be (I myself would certainly like that), but that is not the issue – the issue is that it is not the case. The European project has, to a good extent even purposefully, dodged the creation of a European identity, and it is just absurd to claim now that there should be one, or even that it should come about because of the crisis. So, even if a higher inflation (even a mildly higher one than exists) were desirable on a European level, on the German level, it is not. A vast majority of Germans do not feel pan-European solidarity to the extent that they want to finance other countries, especially if those – especially Greece – are reported again and again to have brought their economic problems largely upon themselves by corruption and leisure orientation, even if that was well-known but calculatedly ignored by the EU and its other member countries.
All this means that Germany’s stand against inflation is not a case of an evil elite imposing wrong economics on a witless and hapless people, but of politicians representing the well-considered self-interest of their electorate (although it would appear anachronistic to most Germans to ascribe any sort of competence and policy design to the Merkel government right now). And this, in return, is, as I stated just a moment ago, close to the very definition of democracy. One may call it populism, but democracy necessarily entails a popular element.
One may not like any of this, but the problem then is elsewhere. It is in the missing European identity in Germany (and elsewhere), the missing willingness to part with one’s money, a lack of empathy, a lack of leadership – but under the current circumstances, the fact that Germans generally don’t want any inflation of what for them is primarily their currency is as normal as it is that the German leadership therefore doesn’t push, or at least consent to, inflation either, or at the very least, hesitates and delays. It has nothing to do with the legacy of the hyperinflation of 1922-1923, which, if anything, is simply used as an illustration among those in the German discourse who are already familiar with the topic. If one minds the German position and thinks it should be revised, one would be wiser to think about arguments addressing the genuine – and rational – German concerns over inflation, rather than whining about the power of a myth that, in the way it is claimed to, does not even exist.